Capital Punishment: A Penalty by Death...

INTRODUCTION
Man has come to find himself in existence. This was not out of his decision but he has received it. He has also come to live with others in the society. The implication to the foregoing is that man should co-habit with others in the society. In his stay in the society, he has experienced the wonders of good, the ubiquity of evil and other complexities of his existence. All this has caused human being, especially philosophers, to ponder upon the nature human person.
This is an argument of ages: Is capital punishment right or wrong?
On various accounts, human person has been defined as a rational being within available alternatives, a being that is free, makes choice, and stands responsible for his or her choice. In line with this, human person is conceived of as a being with such indispensable ingredients as rationality, availability of alternatives, choice, freewill, responsibility and moral responsibility, morality, inalienability, and inviolability. These qualities ascribed to human being qualify him/her as a moral agent. In a bid to define a moral agent, G.O Ozumba writes that “a moral agent must be free and responsible, imbued with certain maturity, rationality and sensitivity” (Ethics, 3). Resounding intellectual witness to the position of G.O Ozumba above, Dr. Ekanola asserts that many factors give relevance and meaning to morality viz; human rationality, choice (that is the ability to make choice), scarce resources (raising the question of who gets what, when and how?), and the fact of social interaction.
The idea of responsibility identifies actions as either good or bad, right or wrong, praise-worthy or blame-worthy, worthy of reward or punishable. This means that punishment (in whatever nature or name) is an intrinsic attribute of human person and therefore, a social concept. This leads us to the crux of this research – capital punishment.
In this research therefore, the aim is to make critical analysis of the concept of punishment with emphasis on capital punishment. This will guide us into interrogating the ideas in various arguments (both in support and against) on the phenomenon of capital punishment. The background of this research is an aim to ascertain the reality of the subject matter – capital punishment - regarding its nature and to seek a possible way of appropriating the result in accomplishing the role of philosophy in terms of problem solving in the human society.

CAPITAL PUNISHMENT

Before we go into our consideration of capital punishment, let us attempt our commonsense with the following story-line;
On Halloween night 1989, a group of eight young men attacked Kimberley Rae Harbor in the Dorchester section of Boston, according to newspaper reports she was carried into a vacant field, gang raped, stabbed over 130 times with knives and broken bottles, beaten with a tree limb, kicked, stomped on, and then left to die in a puddle of blood (Wellman, morals, 242).
In certainty, if these men were to be brought to us for judgment, almost everybody will affirm that the only commensurate punishment for their heinous crime will be death. This is an idea of capital punishment.
Capital punishment is variously called “the death penalty” or “execution”. It is the killing of a person by judicial process for reasons of retribution or deterrence.  Its history dates back to ages. Different societies in history have adopted the institution of capital punishment on instances of crime. Such crimes for which death penalty is resorted to are known as “capital crimes” or “capital offences”. Some of the offences that attract capital punishment are murder, rape, drug trafficking and treason. Many nations are currently agitating for the abolition of capital punishment while orders argued for its retention in the penal codes.
Our objective in this research centers on moral justification of capital punishment. Is it ought or ought not to be supported? Can there be any circumstance that grants capital punishment as ever right? Can it ever be morally justifiable to punish any crime with death? These questions are such that call up and awake the thinking of the moral agent. Nobody can answer them in a hurry hence, they request critical reconsideration. We now turn to arguments that bother on capital punishment.

ARGUMENTS IN SUPPORT OF CAPITAL PUNISHMENT

Many arguments have been brought forward in an attempt to give justification to capital punishment. We attempt to explore some of the arguments in what follows.
(a)      BIBLICAL INSTANCES
Most supporters of the death penalty have severally pointed to their grounds as the bible. They assert that passages of the bible abound that give substantiation to it. One of the examples is “whoever strikes a person mortally shall be put to death” (Exodus 21:12). The bible also gives similar injunction against such crime like kidnapping. Writing in support to the argument above, Carl Wellman in his book “”Morals and Ethics” posits that “…. Christians and Jews claim that not only does God permit the death penalty but that in certain cases such as murder, God requires the death penalty” (247).

(b)      RETRIBUTION
Arguments for capital punishment from the point of view of retribution are based on the equation of the punishment to the crime. For the retributionists, to strike a moral balance, the punishment must be proportional to the evil perpetuated by the criminal. In this regard they maintain that only death can balance death. In concurrence with this, Emmett Barcalow asserts;
…this means that the punishment should fit the crime, that the evil inflicted upon the condemned criminal should be in proportion to the degree of harm he has done. Since the only penalties bad enough to equate the greatest crime is death, and since justice requires that the criminal receive just retribution for his past misdeeds, and since it is right to do what justice requires, capital punishment is sometimes right (Moral, 247).
Furthermore, similar grounds were posited by Immanuel Kant thus,
If…he has committed murder he must die. Here, there is no substitute that will satisfy justice. There is no similarity between life however wretched it may be…. This fitting punishment to the crime… is shown by the fact that only by this is a sentence of death pronounced on every criminal in proportion to his inner wickedness (Doctrine, 142).

(c)      SOCIAL PROTECTION AND PREVENTION
Arguments have been proposed in support of capital punishment for purposes of social protection or prevention of subsequent recurrence. The argument here is that if one has ever done a thing in the first instance, there is every possibility of repetition. For this class of argumentators, the only way that guarantees that the criminal does not murder or rape again is death penalty. It is possible, they argue, for the criminal in life sentence to kill the inmates or even visitors. He can also escape to continue his act of murder or otherwise.
(d)      DETERRENCE
Beyond preventing the criminal from subsequent performance of crimes, the death penalty deters other people from similar engagements. Human beings sometimes fail to do evil or avoid it for fear of punishment. This implies that the more severe the punishment is, the more it deters people from performing crimes that attract them. Since all human beings are sincerely afraid of death, capital punishment provides a more viable means of deterring people from committing crimes.

ARGUMENTS AGAINST CAPITAL PUNISHMENT

Issues of moral importance always seem to generate arguments from both sides in a way that tend to look balanced. They usually provoke moral intellectualization in such manner of plausible presentation across positions and sides. If any moral issue does not arouse or cause arguments in the form as highlighted above, then it does not constitute any moral problem. Capital punishment is one of such issues that ignite real arguments on both sides. Let us now consider arguments that do not favor capital punishment.
(a)      ARGUMENTS FROM MORALITY
Most moral philosophers have argued that even if it is granted that capital punishment is an effective deterrence against crimes, it does not make it to acquire the tincture of moral acceptability. For them, capital punishment amounts to nothing short of murder. In this regard, they assert that capital punishment is the violation of moral law since it holds that the killing of human kind is wrong. This, according to them, derives from the inalienability and inviolability of the human person. Therefore, since capital punishment involves the killing of the human kind, then it is morally unjustifiable and therefore wrong in all instances.
(b)      MISCARRIAGE OF JUSTICE  
The argument under miscarriage of justice is multifaceted. It runs in many spectra. Firstly, there can be error in judgment based on mistake of evidence(s). Secondly, there can be suppression of truth through intimidation and other kinds of corruption. Thirdly, there might be incapacitation or other influences that hinder justice. Fourthly, the economic condition or situation can allow one to hire a solicitor that is ineffective. On the whole, since the totality of the judicial system is based on technical knock-out, some solicitors are more endowed in skill than others even when they are clearly defending the wrong. All this can lead to the execution of an innocent person. Appealing to discrimination as an influence that can lead to miscarriage of justice, Hugh D. Barlow gives an account in the United States thus; “more blacks than whites have been executed, and nearly 90 percent of those who died for rape were blacks” (Introduction, 497).
(c)      IRREMEDIABILITY AND MORAL TRAGEDY
This argument derives from the foregoing. For this argument, capital punishment is wrong because it cannot be remedied. This can be experienced in the case of judicial error. If one who is innocent was wrongfully convicted and the truth was to be discovered afterwards, there remains no act of remedy since the life of the innocent must have been taken already. This is a moral tragedy. This, they argue, is worse than setting a million convicts free. It would be better to set millions of criminals free than wrongfully executing an innocent one. Life imprisonment for this argument is preferable since it can give room for remedy in such circumstance. Capital punishment for this reason is always wrong.
(d)      DETERRENCE AND EFFECTIVENESS
For moral thinkers who oppose capital punishment for purposes of deterrence, capital punishment is a less deterrent measure against crimes than a high degree of detection and conviction. The question here is why wouldn’t the threat of death be a greater deterrent than the threat of long prison sentence? Peter Greenwood in his article “The Violent Offenders in the Criminal Justice System” proffered an answer to the question as he puts forward that “If people believe that the probability of being apprehended, convicted, and punished is low, crime rises; if people believe that the probability of being apprehended, convicted, and punished is high, crime declines” (339-340). According to this position, it might not matter so much regarding the severity of the punishment than it is important with reference to people knowing that there exists a high degree of their being detected, convicted, and punished. This poses a challenge of efficiency to the security and judicial systems respectively. When people know that they cannot escape punishment, the result is a higher deterrence than capital punishment.
(e)      ARGUMENT AGAINST RETRIBUTION
Those who oppose death penalty disagree that it is the more appropriate kind of punishment for even the most depraved criminal. They argue that the view of retribution flows from primitive passions and emotions. Such primitive passions and emotions include fear, hatred, and strong desire for revenge.  These emotions, according to them, do not derive from reason or any kind of humane feelings. They hold that  such emotional push  are natural in human beings that they tend to be more justified in feeling outrage in proportion to the degree of brutality and cruelty of the crime committed against them.

CRITIQUE AND CONCLUSION

Human beings have been characterized by the fundamental right to life and the feature of inviolability. This is a fact that both sides in the ongoing argument on capital punishment will not deny. This can be held as the heart of the subject matter. Differences in conceptions, as have been made evident in the arguments, derive from interpretations and understanding of the aforementioned characteristics and features of the human person – right to life and the inviolability of human person. All claims are made with reference to background or inclination. But the fact remains that capital punishment is a real moral problem.
The arguments from both sides seem to balance. This calls for our reappraisal of the positions so far. It has to be pointed out here that the Christian position regarding capital punishment is not clear. While some passages from the bible seem to support capital punishment, some tend to rebuff it as wrong. Jesus clearly repudiated the Old Testament requirement of “life for life, eye for eye” as follows;
You have heard that it was said, “An eye for an eye and a tooth for a tooth.” But I say to you, do not resist the evildoer. But if anyone strikes your right cheek, turn the other also; and if anyone wants to sue you and take your coat, give your cloak as well (Matthew 5: 38-40).
To further this conception, the sixth commandment reads “Thou Shalt not kill”.  Those who argue from the bible in support of capital punishment warn that meaning should be found in context.  This injunction when meaning should be found in context.  This injunction when taken out of context can be extended to mosquitoes and animals as well.  For them therefore in the context, it can be interpreted as “Thou Shalt not murder”, since it is only unjustified killing that is prohibited by this commandment.
If we appeal to the moral law based on the command theory, which will take us to the Bible injunctions as we have seen above, several criticisms can come up. Firstly, there is the challenge of the content of the moral law. Secondly, question of the existence of the moral laws are possible.
Considering deterrence, one might point out the effect of reforms over time. In the olden days, execution was done publicity and more painful. But reforms have limited all this that the degree of deterrence might be very minimal, even less than life sentence.
Secondly, questions are raised about evidences of the deterrent effect of the death penalty as against other kinds of punishment. Scientific facts prove that they are not as effective as we tend to believe them.
Though these arguments can go on and on, it should be made clear that in as much as personhood is either given or attained, it can also be lost in the process of actions. If human person has the fundamental right to life and is inviolable, any one who takes the life of other must by that act lose his or forfeit it. It should even be viewed as more immoral for one who murdered to think of living. In simple terms, anyone who murders should no longer be seen as a human kind. The right to life should include one’s right to live and the right of others to also live. Also the idea of inviolability should incorporate not being violated and not violating. Then if one should violate the life of the other by his /her act of murder, he/she prima facie violates his/her features of inviolability.
In the last analysis, capital punishment has been exposed as posing strong moral questions. This research holds that although it might be difficult to either prove or disprove that capital punishment has acceptable moral justification, it can be sustained by the principle of retribution and the idea of universalizability of actions in the Kantian Parlance.

REFERENCES
Barcalow, E. Moral Philosophy: Theory and Issues California: Wadsworth Publishing Company, 1994.
Barlow, H.D. Introduction to Criminology.  Glenview, II: Scott Foresman, 1990.
Ekanola, Ethnics and Morality. Class Lecture on Ethnics in University of Ibadan, February.
Greenwood, P. “The Violent Offender in the Criminal Justice System” in: Weiner etal, ed. Violence. 339 – 340. 
Holy Bible: The New Revised Standard Version.
Kant, I. The Doctrine of Right.  In: Gregor, M. (Trans) The Metaphysics of Moral.  New York: Cambridge University press, 1991.
Ozumba, G. O. A Course Text on Ethnics Lagos: Obaroh and Ogbinaka Publishers Ltd, 2001.
Wellman, C. Morals and Ethnics. New Jersey: Prentice Hall Englewood Cliffs, 1988.


KEMKA S. IBEJI
Tel:         +234 803 887 7166
Email:    kingsolkem@gmail.com
Skype:    kemka.ibeji

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

THE OUTLAWS IN THE SOUTHWEST AND THEIR ENABLER: THE AREA BOY CALLED OBA OF LAGOS Written by KEMKA S. IBEJI

COUNTDOWN TO BLISSHALL LAUNCH: A NEW ERA IN ENTERTAINMENT By KIVOrg Editorial

LET US CLING TO THE OLD SCIENCE TILL MODERN SCIENCE CLEARS OUR SUSPICION OF ITS ILLEGITIMATE GIFT TO FEMINISM IN THE SCIENCE OF REPRODUCTION Written by KEMKA S. IBEJI